Pages

Wednesday, May 22, 2013

Dawkins and Plantinga on Design

by Benny Mattis

 In The God Delusion, Richard Dawkins argues that the "argument from improbability" (a type of argument that infers metaphysical truths from the existence of high levels of complexity in the world, usually enlisted in the defense of theism and named the "Argument from Design" or the "Design Argument"), "properly deployed, comes close to proving that God does not exist" (137). "It is indeed a very strong and, I suspect, unanswerable argument," Dawkins claims, "But in precisely the opposite direction from the theist's intention" (137). Christian philosopher Alvin Plantinga, on the other hand, shows in Where the Conflict Really Lies that the Design Argument is actually not very strong, due to the weakness of its premises, yet still considers it ultimately a case of "concord" between religion and science (264). Dawkins succeeds in showing that the argument from improbability best functions as support for atheism, but Plantinga succeeds in showing that the argument is not very strong in the first place.
Undercutting Theism
Before addressing the strength or weakness of the argument from improbability, it would be constructive to present the most common historical instance of it (as the Argument from Design for theism), and whether it actually supports theism or atheism (in the latter case as Dawkins' "Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit"). As for the former question, Dawkins lays out his interpretation of the argument with characteristic scorn:
Creationist 'logic' is always the same. Some natural phenomenon is too statistically improbable, too complex, too beautiful, too awe-inspiring to have come about by chance. Design is the only alternative to chance that the [Creationist] authors can imagine. Therefore a designer must have done it. (146)
This interpretation of Dawkins' might be put more formally as such:
1) There exists a being x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance.
2) For any x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance, there exists an explanation y such that (y explains how the level of complexity in x obtained in this world) and (y posits the existence of a designer for x).
3) So, there exists an explanation y such that y posits the existence of a designer for x.
Dawkins takes issue with (2); indeed, given (1), (2) directly contradicts Dawkins' belief that designers in general are not explanatory of complexity:
(NE) For any being x, there does not exist any explanation d such that (d posits a designer of x) and (d explains how the level of complexity in x obtained in this world).
This is because, as Dawkins states, design "raises an even bigger problem than it solves: who designed the designer?" (147). "Design doesn't explain organized complexity," Plantinga says in summarizing Dawkins' point; "It presupposes it, because the designer would have to be as complex as what it creates" (26). An explanation that presupposes what it explains is not explanatory at all; hence, Dawkins' assertion that design hypotheses are not explanatory of high levels of complexity.
Despite his apparent understanding of Dawkins' undercutting defeater for design hypotheses, however, Plantinga challenges Dawkins' logic with an anecdote involving a science fiction scenario:
Suppose we land on an alien planet...and discover some machine-like objects that look and work just like a 1941 Allis Chalmers tractor; our leader says 'there must be intelligent beings on this planet--look at those tractors.' A sophomore philosophy student on the expedition objects: 'Hey, hold on a minute! You have explained nothing at all! Any intelligent life that designed those tractors would have to be at least as complex as they are!' No doubt we'd tell him a little learning is a dangerous thing and advise him to take the next rocket ship home and enroll in another philosophy course or two. (27)
Plantinga here appears to be likening the Design Argument's proponent's reasoning with that of the space expedition's team leader, and Professor Dawkins' reasoning with that of an exceedingly foolish undergraduate. To make this analogy more complete, we need only consider the space expedition's resident theologian, who, upon seeing the tractors, confidently proclaimed that they constituted evidence for God and, indeed, "concord" between space travel and theistic religion.
"The point is we aren't trying to give an ultimate explanation of organized complexity," explains Plantinga, "and we aren't trying to explain organized complexity in general; we are only trying to explain one particular manifestation of it...it is perfectly proper to explain one manifestation of organized complexity in terms of another" (28). Indeed, the expedition leader could so properly explain the occurrence of those tractors as such by appealing to a designer, but Dawkins also allows that the occurrence of particular complex biological machines we see on earth might be discovered to be best explained by a designer. "It may even be a superhuman designer," imagines Dawkins, "but, if so, it will most certainly not be a designer who just popped into existence, or who always existed" (186). Such an unexplained being would in some sense explain the occurrence of the complex tractor, or a complex biological machine, but not the occurrence of their particular levels of complexity as such (because to posit their existence would require presupposing even greater levels of complexity, begging the question), and this is "the problem that any theory of life must solve" (145). We are not trying to explain tractors as such in the way the expedition leader did, or complexity "in general" as Plantinga suggests, but rather the level of complexity as such instantiated in the tractor, i.e., why a particular observed level of complexity has obtained in this world.
In another attempt to prevent Dawkins' undercutting defeat of the Design Argument for theism, Plantinga suggests that God is not, in fact, complex. Disputing Dawkins' argument in The God Delusion, Plantinga digs up Dawkins' definition of complexity from The Blind Watchmaker: "Something is complex if it has parts that are 'arranged in a way that is unlikely to have arisen by chance alone.' Here he's clearly thinking of material objects" (29). Plantinga then lays out a clear logical demonstration of God's simplicity:
1) "Immaterial objects, e.g. numbers, don't have parts."
2) "God is...an immaterial spiritual being."
3) "Hence God has no parts at all."
4) If something has no parts, then it is not complex, according to Dawkins' definition of complexity.
5) So, God is not complex, according to Dawkins' definition of complexity. (27)
This argument is simple enough, but any logician will immediately notice the vagueness of (1); while it is evident that some immaterial objects don't have parts, Plantinga presumably intends to claim that all immaterial objects don't have parts, which is certainly not sufficiently justified by the single example of numbers (unless, of course, all immaterial objects are numbers, but this option would be less than helpful to Plantinga).
Setting aside the question of whether an immaterial entity could have parts, it is worth pointing out that Dawkins clearly does not intend for his definition of complexity (presumably based in biology) in The Blind Watchmaker to be applied in The God Delusion as well; indeed, Dawkins even refers to theologian Keith Ward's statement that "It is quite coherent...to suppose that God, while internally indivisible, is internally complex," indicating a broader concept of complexity than in his preceding writings on biology (179). "God may not have a brain made of neurones," insists Dawkins, "or a CPU made of silicon, but if he has the powers attributed to him he must have something far more elaborately and non-randomly constructed than the largest brain or the largest computer we know" (184). Even if God is an immaterial substance (as God presumably is a concrete person, and not an abstract entity such as a number), as a designer capable of intending the entire actual world he would have to be (in some way) more complex than the actual world itself, since his own intention would be as complex as the world is insofar as it is designed (i.e., insofar as God intends it). Even an immaterial God, claims Dawkins, would not be a legitimate explanation for the levels of complexity we observe in the world; in this Dawkins brings an undercutting defeater to theistic belief based on the Argument from Design for theism.
Rebutting Theism
It seems that a designer capable of intending every designed aspect of the world would have to be at least as complex as the world is insofar it is designed; this is why positing the existence of such a designer is not explanatory of the high level of complexity in the universe. Dawkins, however, does not stop with this mere undercutting defeat, but rather continues on to say that "The argument from improbability, properly deployed, comes close to proving that God does not exist" (137). This proper deployment, intended as a rebutting defeater for theism, is what Dawkins refers to as the Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit.
Dawkins credits Fred Hoyle with positing a Boeing 747 as the archetypal example of organized complexity (138). According to Dawkins' reasoning, any possible designer of a being as complex as a 747 (let's call the 747-like object Bn, where Bn+1 is more complex than Bn, which is more complex than Bn-1, and so forth) would have to be more complex than the object itself (that is, it would correspond with Bn+x, where x is some number greater than zero). If God existed, then presumably, God would be the designer of all of the other designers in the universe; thus, he would quite properly be called the ultimate designer, or the Ultimate Boeing 747, as Dawkins suggests (138). However, the logical end of the Design Argument, unaided by the possibility of unguided evolution, "presents an infinite regress from which [God] cannot help us escape" (136).
Dawkins has shown the incoherence in premise (2) of his Design Argument (i.e., the failure of intentional explanations to explain complexity as such), but it can still work if we replace it with
2') For any x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance, there exists an explanation y such that (y explains how x occurs in this world) and (y posits the existence of a designer for x).
This crucial update to the Design Argument might be summed up essentially in a single premise, where Bn+1 is more complex than Bn, which is more complex than Bn-1, and so forth:
DA) If there is a complex being Bn, then there is a being Bn+1 that designed Bn.
The infinite regress only needs a 747 to be put in motion:
B1) There is a complex being Bn (for example, a Boeing 747)
B2) There is a being Bn+1 that designed Bn (Modus Ponens DA, B1)
B3) There is a being Bn+2 that designed Bn+1 (MP DA, B2)
B4) There is a being Bn+3 that designed Bn+2 (MP DA, B3)
...
BU) There is a being BU that designed BU-1 (MP DA, B(U-1))
Where BU is an 'ultimate' designer, i.e. the Ultimate Boeing 747. Of course, given (DA) as it is, U will be a limit towards infinity, rather than a determinate quantity P. This can be shown easily enough via reductio ad absurdum:
A1) Suppose there is a complex being BP such that BP is the ultimate designer.
A2) There is a being BP+1 that designed BP (MP DA, A1)
A3) If (A2), then BP is not the ultimate designer.
A3) So, A1 is false, and there is a complex being BP+1 such that BP+1 is the ultimate designer.
The existence of an ultimate designer BU is preserved from (A1) to (A3), but U continuously increases greater than any finite quantity assigned to it. Since U is a limit towards infinity, and BU would be the ultimate designer, it follows from the necessity of greater complexity in designers (and the significance of our subscripts stated above) that BU's complexity is a limit towards infinity, and thus that an ultimate designer would be infinitely complex. This is why, as Dawkins claims with his Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit, "There almost certainly is no God" (137).
Given the reasoning behind the Design Argument, the existence of God would be infinitely unlikely, as God would be infinitely complex. However, without the possibility of ultimate designers (which demand explanation) arising from primeval simplicity (which does not demand explanation), it also remains utterly mysterious and itself apparently vastly improbable. This is where evolution comes in: the theory of evolution reveals how high levels of complexity could arise in such a universe, because it replaces (2') with
2'') For any x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance, there exists an explanation y such that (y posits a designer for x) or (y posits the evolution of x through evolution by natural selection, explaining its level of complexity).
and replaces (DA) with
DA') If there is a complex being Bn, then there is a being Bn+1 that designed Bn, or Bn evolved out of primeval simplicity.
(DA') does not lend itself to a necessary infinite regress, but allows for an ultimate designer BU, as long as it evolved out of primeval simplicity. The God of theism would not have evolved out of primeval simplicity, so this still means that any ultimate designer would not be the God of theism. Thus, evolution on atheism provides an explanation for high levels of complexity in the universe, whereas no such explanation can be given on theism regardless of its compatibility with science; all else being equal, the argument from improbability suggests that evolution constitutes evidence for atheism. Dawkins succeeds in showing that the reasoning behind the Design Argument best serves atheism, rather than theism.
Deflecting Dawkins
The argument from improbability against theism, in the form of Dawkins' Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit, suggests that theism is almost certainly false. Its premises, however, are weak, and Plantinga demonstrates this in his critique of Dawkins as well as his critique of theistic applications of the argument. The premises of his Gambit can be formulated as such:
1) There exists a being x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance.
2'') For any x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance, there exists an explanation y such that (y posits a designer for x) or (y posits the evolution of x through evolution by natural selection, explaining its level of complexity).
3) If (1) and (2''), then God's existence is infinitely improbable.
4) So, God's existence is infinitely improbable.
Dawkins claims that his Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit "does not depend on subjective judgment" (136), but this belief of Dawkins', as Plantinga demonstrates, is manifestly false.
Premise (2) and its derivatives (2', 2'', DA, and DA') are where the subjectivity really lies. Dawkins never justifies the notion that there simply must be an explanation for the occurrence of a given level of complexity; he simply assumes that it "is one thing on which we can all agree" (145). He vaguely motions elsewhere that "sometimes the language of information theory is used" in justifying the principle that complexity must have an explanation, but seems to take the principle as self-evident throughout his argument (138). Unfortunately, Dawkins' justification for (2'') is at best inter-subjective, and inter-subjective in a consensus that does not include a certain prominent Christian philosopher.
"Explanations come to an end," Plantinga writes, and "for theism they come to an end in God" (28). So, even given that "mind would be an outstanding example of organized complexity" (27), according to theism there is no explanation for the existence of a mind (28), and so there is no explanation for why that level of complexity obtained in the world. Plantinga points out that "the materialist...doesn't have an explanation for the existence of elementary particles" (28). Dawkins predicts this rebuttal to (2) by suggesting that "Some kind of multiverse theory could in principle do for physics the same explanatory work as Darwinism does for biology" (188). Realizing the unconvincing nature of this response, Dawkins adds that "the anthropic principle entitles us to postulate far more luck than our limited human intuition is comfortable with" (188). Until such a multiverse theory is explicated, however, Dawkins' justification for the expectation of explanation of complexity remains a mere 'reason of the gaps.'
Plantinga also brings up the common notion that "It is not so much as possible that there is no such person as God...[Dawkins] owes us an argument...that there is no necessary being with the attributes of God" (30). Presumably, Plantinga is not suggesting that Dawkins seriously consider whether God necessarily exists, when the question of God's existence is what is up for debate in the first place; the most charitable interpretation of Plantinga here would take this comment as an objection to (2''). Plantinga might be suggesting that theism actually offers another way out of the infinite regress mentioned above, because it actually posits
(2''') For any x such that x is too complex to have come about by chance, there exists an explanation y such that (y posits a designer for x) or (y posits the evolution of x through evolution by natural selection) or (y posits that x exists necessarily).
Some instances of complexity, and thus some high levels of complexity as such, might not be contingent on designers or evolution; indeed, they might be necessary occurrences or brute fact.
Plantinga succeeds in undermining Dawkins' rationales for (2) and its derivatives, showing them ultimately to be based on little more than personal opinion. Since Dawkins "can't get excited about personal opinions" (136), perhaps he should not get too excited about his argument from the improbability of complexity (the "Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit"), either.
Conclusion
The argument from improbability, historically presented as the theistic Argument from Design, has been used throughout the ages to convince skeptics of the existence of God. Richard Dawkins claimed that it is a strong argument, but rather a strong argument against theism as the Ultimate Boeing 747 Gambit; Dawkins succeeded in demonstrating his latter point, but Christian philosopher of religion Alvin Plantinga showed that the argument from improbability is not strong in the objective sense that Dawkins intended. A commitment to impartiality turns the Design Argument against theism, but also reveals it as ultimately based in subjective intuition.

Sources
Dawkins, Richard. The God Delusion. Great Britain: Bantam, 2006. Print.
Plantinga, Alvin. Where the Conflict Really Lies. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. Print.

No comments:

Post a Comment

What did you think?