Pages

Monday, June 25, 2012

A Maze of Mirrors

by Benny Mattis

I recently watched a TED talk about mirror neurons, newly discovered brain cells that "reflect" the brain activity of other people.  When a particular action is performed, a specific corresponding neural firing pattern is, unsurprisingly, consistently conjoined with the performance of that action.  There is a subset of these activated neurons, called the mirror neurons, that is also activated when someone else is seen performing the action in question.  So, if "firing pattern X" is the activity observed in my brain when I open a door, a part of that pattern will also show up when I'm watching someone else open a door.  Upon observing me performing the action, roughly the same cluster of mirror neurons will be excited in their own brain, as well.

I think a good example of how these neurons presumably work is found in competitive rowing.  Crew is one sport that cannot be taught in books; the proper movements feel unnatural at first, and must be synchronized with everyone else in the boat.  How does this happen?  There are coaches, who definitely play an important role in noticing the shortcomings of each and every team member's technique--after all, mistakes that would be unnoticeable to an uneducated observer could make a noticeable impact over the course of a six-kilometer race.  But how do they point out flaws in technique?  Words usually aren't very useful, so they set the novice rowers in a place where they can view the varsity team.  When a novice is doing something incorrectly, they point to a varsity rower and say "See the way Jim is keeping his back at an angle?  Do that."  By seeing Jim's correct technique in action, the novice learns more than they ever could from mere language or still pictures.

Is this extra learning capacity the result of mirror neurons?  That's certainly a possibility.  In fact, Vilayanur Ramachandran suggests in the TED talk that these specific cells may have enabled us to accelerate the proliferation of tool use, shelter-building skills, language, and other technical knowledge for the last few hundred thousand years.   The idea is basically that mirror neurons turned us into evolutionary X-Men, building our civilization through technological (in the broadest sense of the word) leaps and bounds rather than slow hereditary adaptations.  If this is true, the ability to imitate others is a pillar of our modern industrial civilization.

Enter Isak Gerson.  In January of 2012, the then 19-year-old Swedish student succeeded in gaining official recognition from the Swedish government for the Missionary Church of Kopimism, a "religion" built around the practice of file-sharing.  The principles of Kopimism are posted on the Church's website:
-All knowledge to all
-The search for knowledge is sacred
-The circulation of knowledge is sacred
-The act of copying is sacred
In an interview with New Scientist, Gerson discloses that the Kopimists "worship the value of information by copying it."  Questioned about a Kopimist belief in the afterlife, Gerson responded: "Information doesn't really have a life, but I guess it can be forgotten, but as long as it is copied it won't be."

The apolitical aspects of Kopimism may seem like ad-hoc justifications for an organized illegal file-sharing culture, but I actually find in them a reflection of my own worldview.  My mother, for example, often says that you should be kind to others, follow the golden rule, etc. because others may end up imitating you, beginning a chain reaction of negativity.  Everyone is copying everyone else, and from this arises a sort of crude community-wide karmic reaction to nastiness.  To me, at least, this seems like one of the best ways to convince a hedonist to follow the golden rule.  A Kopimist basis for morality, perhaps?

Even eternal life is granted in some way through the communication of thoughts between people--as V proclaims in V for Vendetta (Warner Bros., 2005), "Ideas are bulletproof."  People looking for immortality usually don't care much about the fact that their matter and energy can't be destroyed--they want their phenomenal experience, what it is like to be them, to escape that very embodiment of mass and energy, even when it can no longer pump oxygen to the brain.  But what is language but the very transfer of this mental content?  Singularitarians like Ray Kurzweil want us to upload our souls into computers for eternal life, but the extent to which language actually communicates ideas is the extent to which we've already achieved this futuristic goal.  Who can listen to a particularly moving love song without feeling what it was like for the songwriter?  How can we even speak of "love" without communicating a complex mixture of feelings to the listener?  Of course, language isn't perfect, and this truth isn't likely to sate Kurzweil's appetite for immortality.  But there is more to earthly immortality than just a conscious memory of the dead; their habits and ideas, uploaded and preserved through spoken language and mirror neurons, could very well prolong the survival of what it was like to be them.

One must always be careful when mixing science with religion, and I suspect all this talk about immortality and karma sounds like a desperate pseudoscientific attempt at the resuscitation of dead gods.  Clearly, these things aren't the same as supernatural immortality or karma as found in popular Christianity or Buddhism, but they are facts about reality that do have similar consequences as--and grounds for analogy with--those religious concepts.  The importance of mirror neurons is that they show how these duplications of phenomenal information might transcend, and likely precede, the requirements of shared language or even shared species.

Thursday, June 21, 2012

Free Materials

by Benny Mattis

It is overwhelmingly evident that human beings are made entirely of physical material.  I think it's also safe to assume that physical material is made of molecules, which in turn are made of atoms, which in turn are made of subatomic particles, which operate in accordance with the laws of physics.  Consequently, reason leads one to believe that human beings operate according to the laws of physics.

Many people find this conclusion disturbing.  They notice that there's "no room" for something called "free will," and if they don't find evidence for this phantasm they may take personal issue with the way the world works.  If they've already boxed themselves into a naturalistic worldview, they might twist the usual meaning of "free will" in a sort of reverse-Wizard-of-Oz tactic: "Don't worry, everyone!  Despite what Newton told you, there's still a mind behind the curtain of deterministic interactions!"  But even Heisenberg's uncertainty principle doesn't save free will; as various commenters on Michio Kaku's YouTube opinion noted, mere uncertainty of action is clearly not the same as freedom of will.

What, then, is it that would really count as free will?  If any being had a will transcendent of material forces, it would be God.  The Catholic Encyclopedia, however, states that God is incapable of choosing evil.  This is further backed up by James 1:13 ("God cannot be tempted with evil" [NIV]) and Hebrews 6:18 ("It is impossible for God to lie" [NIV]), at least for Bible-believing theists.  So God would be bound by his perfect nature.  But how is this any different from the material human, who is free to do anything within his or her natural constraints?  A human is free to try whatever they want--that is, whatever actions to which their neurons are disposed.  They are not free to act contrary to their own neurologically-embodied desires, and they are not free to transcend the laws of physics.  It seems like the search for ideal freedom only leads back to some form of determinism; as Schopenhauer noted, "Man can do what he wills but he cannot will what he wills."

But does this mean that we are totally helpless passengers on a runaway train of atoms?  Does this mean that, as Sam Harris claims in The Moral Landscape, "Each one of us is like a phenomenological glockenspiel played by an invisible hand" (104)?  I don't think it's quite that simple, though I do appreciate Harris's use of funny words to illustrate his point.

I think Harris's incompatibilist view of determinism is incorrect precisely insofar as it is dualistic--and it actually is dualistic.  He compares the brain and the mind to the musician and their instrument respectively, but this analogy subtly separates the brain and the mind into two separate objects capable of existing independently.  If Harris's own monistic view is valid, it is nonsensical to claim that we are being played by our own neurons, because we are our neurons.  We are ourselves agents of change in the deterministic machine.  There is no glockenspiel.


Monday, June 18, 2012

Some Thoughts on Prometheus

by Benny Mattis

[SPOILER ALERT]

I saw Ridley Scott's amazing Prometheus today, and it was as thrilling as I expected.  There was, however, an unexpected theme--that of faith and its relationship with science.

Scott made sure we saw that the heroine, Dr. Elizabeth Shaw, had faith.  She was one of the very few people on the expedition who weren't completely cynical in the beginning, and held an attachment to her cross necklace despite scorn from the android David and patronizing disbelief from her boyfriend Charlie.  But was this a message specifically endorsing Christianity?  Has Ridley Scott started taking cues from Focus on the Family?  I don't think so.  The faith that Dr. Shaw acted on in the movie had nothing to do with Jesus in particular, but was placed in the mission she was on.  I think her cross necklace was just a reminder that there is a faith shared by naturalists and supernaturalists alike--faith, that is, in the interpretability of reality.

Science itself is not justified by mere science.  As shown in the movie, it can lead to disastrous consequences, and there is no guarantee that answers will be obtained.  In fact, inductive reasoning--the cornerstone of a naturalistic worldview--would lead one to doubt the efficacy of any kind of scientific investigation.  Take DNA, for example:  Up until the structure of DNA was first discovered (presumably by Crick and Watson), nobody had ever before succeeded in doing such a thing.  Every discovery, every new invention of humanity, is a violation of the inductive premise that what has never happened in the past will continue not to happen in the future.  To put in so much work towards something that may not even be possible to achieve requires great faith in one's own ability to discover the truth.

Even more important than one's own ability to discover the truth is the discoverability of truth itself.  This is where science and religion share the faith that is missing from Nietzsche and others who say that "There is simply no true world."  "Not all perspectives are equally valid," say the scientists.  "We strive for objective truth."  And what is the religious call to compassion and love for all but a call to view things from God's eyes, being fully aware of the suffering of others around the world?  In a way, the scientist and theist (I know they aren't mutually exclusive categories) are both just trying to submit their own perspectives to a God's-eye view of the world.  The theist thinks that this perspective has been instantiated in at least one existing mind already; the atheistic scientist, on the other hand, in a way believes in God without believing that God exists.  It's the faith shared by these people--the belief without evidence in the potentiality of an obtainable "true" perspective--that separates Dr. Shaw from David the android, who doesn't understand why she keeps seeking answers in the face of unimaginable horror.

However, it was also faith which led the decrepit Peter Weyland to awaken the evil aliens in hopes that they would grant him eternal life.  Weyland, a perfect foil to young female Shaw, exemplified the dark side of faith.  He was not engaged in an analysis of evidence, but a flight from it--the whole mission is a result of his inability to accept death, and he ignores Shaw's warnings about the violent intentions of their newfound extraterrestrial Engineers.  Like the religious fanatic who 'wouldn't want to live in a world where [holy book X] was not true,' Weyland's insatiable lust for eternal life leads him to bring about the destruction of his ship and almost of the entire human species.  Living in what Jean-Paul Sartre called "Bad Faith," Weyland is continually in a state of lying to himself.

But where does Prometheus come into all of this?  Prometheus was the Titan who tried to bring fire from the gods to the humans, putting them on equal ground.  Is Dr. Shaw Prometheus in this story, saving Homo sapiens from its very creators and forever seeking forbidden truths with the faith she has in humanity's potential?  Or is Weyland the typical Prometheus, who tries to get fire from the gods but ends up being brutally punished by them (and rightly so)?  Maybe the two of them are supposed to be representative of Prometheus as a noble hero and Prometheus as an arrogant fool--two possible spins on the original story.  In any case, I thought the movie was worth a watch.

Thursday, June 14, 2012

The Transportation Freedom Administration

by Benny Mattis

Benjamin Franklin once wrote that "They who can give up essential liberty to obtain a little temporary safety, deserve neither liberty nor safety."  A popular right-libertarian propaganda pamphlet entitled Inclined to Liberty: The Futile Attempt to Suppress the Human Spirit posits that "There are those inclined to liberty--freedom of the individual to live his or her life in any peaceful way.  And there are those who are inclined to mastery--permitting others to live their lives only as another sees fit."  In Star Wars Episode III: The Phantom Menace, the evil Emperor Palpatine justifies his reign by promising a "Sehf and secuah societeh;" the virtuous Senator Amidala responds in disappointment that "This is how liberty dies...with thunderous applause."  American culture is teeming with heroic assertions of universal freedom such as these; if I were ever given a choice between the vital joy of freedom and the stagnant decay of mere security, I would hope to choose the former without hesitation.

Fortunately, I don't think I ever will have to make such a decision.  This is not because I plan to live in the wilderness, escaping pesky questions of politics and the other downers of civil society.  It's because the whole freedom-versus-security dichotomy is itself about as meaningful as that of the Quarter Pounder versus the Hamburger Royal.  In politics, freedom and security are the same thing.

Political freedom is the security to act in spite of those who would fight for you to do otherwise.  Freedom to own and trade property property is security from those who would take it by force; national security for the U.S. today is freedom from the rule of distant theocrats.  Freedom from oppression is security from a potential oppressor, and therefore a limitation on their freedom to oppress.  It seems like the will to freedom and the will to security could just be different names for what Nietzsche called the "Will to Power."

Does this mean that the overall increase of freedom, and consequently of security, is impossible on the whole?  Is the whole notion of "progress" actually just various reorganizations of equally oppressive political ideologies?  I don't think so.  The overall power (freedom/security) of a society is increased, for example, with breakthroughs in science and technology, mediated through various methods of education; knowledge is power, and it increases the freedom (to apply that knowledge in the right situation) and security (of knowing how the world works) of every individual in society with sufficient access to it.  A scientifically primitive society will on the whole be less free than an advanced one; a caveman is not free to construct an iPad, regardless of whether he has access to the raw materials necessary.  One could also argue, as Bakunin did, that one is "Truly free only when all human beings, men and women, are equally free;" a somewhat egalitarian distribution of power might then be considered in a way to be more free than an unequal one.

Regardless of these abstract notions on liberty, the apparent similarity of freedom and security in politics raises the question of what it really is that people are defending when they promote one over the other.  It seems, for example, that people often view the movement from freedom to security as a movement from tolerance to totalitarianism.  On the contrary, totalitarianism is the very antithesis of security!  Giving up your right to Habeas Corpus isn't a simple exchange of freedom for security; it is an exchange of every 'normal' citizen's personal security for the increased freedom of certain state officials, in the hopes that they will use it decently.  The caped crusaders of capitalism cry foul at the mention of social safety nets, lamenting oppressive violations of property rights as the desire of the 'lazy' working class for security to be provided by a 'mommy government.'  But what freedom would really be lost?  The freedom to deny a fellow human the medical care they need to survive?  The freedom to beg for charitable donations in the event of an emergency?  These freedoms don't sound awfully different from slavery.

I think that the whole freedom-versus-security dichotomy is basically useless in any serious conversation about political power.  The perspective seems mainly to serve as  justification for authoritarian ideologies, even if the people invoking it are trying to promote liberty.  From now on, though, whenever I hear somebody talking about "freedom," I'm going to try replacing it with "security," and vice versa, seeing if any meaningful difference is made.

Thursday, June 7, 2012

In Defense of Defense as Defense

by Benny Mattis

"Philosophy?  What are you gonna do with that? Become a philosopher?"

So replied a mildly intoxicated stranger (emphasis his) upon hearing of my current major at a recent social gathering.  Most other responses involve more of an attempt at politeness, but when they still end up saying things like 'Well, at least you're going to finish your degree,' the effect is not much different.  The now-expected grimacing expression usually changes when I tell them how effective a major in Philosophy can be in preparing one for graduate school.

Some people seem to use the word "philosophical" as a synonym for "irrelevant;" philosophical problems are certainly not practical, and everyone knows that practical matters have absolutely nothing to do with philosophy.  I doubt the possibility of a more ridiculous notion in a world where people regularly blow themselves up in public in the name of supposedly "philosophical" differences.  Given the obvious relevance of philosophy in this (and every) era, though, the question still remains of "What is it for?"

My interests in philosophy and martial arts developed largely in parallel and in response to their portrayals in pop culture.  The roles of philosopher and martial expert often coincide in the same character, such as Master Splinter from Teenage Mutant Ninja Turtles, the Jedi of Star Wars, or Morpheus of The Matrix.  They're always "wicked cool,"as we say in Massachusetts, and confident in their fighting and thinking ability.  Thus, I came to the conclusion that the purpose of philosophy is to achieve total badassery, which naturally follows from investigating the nature of reality.

Unfortunately, that confidence often translates to total unjustified douchebaggery in practice, and an attitude of elitism among philosophy geeks is a significant cause of its relative lack in general popularity.  So, maybe it would be better to look for answers to this question elsewhere.

Socrates said that philosophy is preparation for death.  I agree with this statement, but not in the way Socrates meant it.  Socrates saw the search for clarity as a way to transcend material existence, but I do not share his contempt for the flesh.

An awareness of death encourages people to give up unnecessary illusions and focus on core issues, or what "really matters."  What is the process of death but the destruction of all the trifling distractions that bog down our everyday lives as time goes by?  Regardless of whether a next life is better, that is no reason to squander one's time here on earth, and the finitude of that time serves as a reminder of this.  The true philosopher, the one who recognizes what is most important in this life and acts accordingly, will have already torn down their illusions to the fullest extent possible, and death's sting of surprise will be lessened if not entirely nullified.  On the other hand, the worldview that relies on falsities and self-contradiction will collapse upon itself when reality closes in.  As Ayn Rand noted, "We can evade reality, but we cannot evade the consequences of evading reality."  And reality, as that which exists even when you stop thinking about it (Philip K. Dick), really does close in on the individual like an experienced martial expert.

So, philosophy for me is like a kind of mental mixed martial arts.  It's a training method by which someone can test the effectiveness of their worldview in making sense of reality, in the same way that MMA tests the effectiveness of various styles in making sense of how best to respond to an immediate threat.  If your style is incomplete or insufficient, you will lose a fight or end up conceding to your opponent in philosophical dialectic, but you can then learn a better style, a new way of looking at things that is more in tune with your personality and that of the opponent (or the truth of reality).

The most serious threats are the street thugs of false propaganda, as opposed to sincere, tournament-registered fellow seekers of truth.  Mixed martial arts may be an attempt to discover the ultimate fighting style, but it's doubtful that one philosophical system or principle will ever encompass all that philosophy aspires to explain.  The original and most relevant purpose of martial arts is reality-based self-defense, and the most relevant use of philosophy is simply to discount various manifestations of nonsensical bullshit.  As C.S. Lewis once said, "Good philosophy must exist, if for no other reason, because bad philosophy needs to be answered."

Tuesday, June 5, 2012

W.W.B.J.S.H.D.

by Benny Mattis

The modern heretic, given an initial rejection of nihilism, is presented with the various religious traditions as the first place to look for answers that cannot be provided by indifferent scientific observation (namely, how one ought to live).  As Hume wrote, you can't derive an "ought" from an "is," and science is only concerned with what is.  But there is a strain in atheism that is less preoccupied by the thrills of deicide and more concerned with helping people come to terms with life without God; Sam Harris is a member of this group, and has been working on adapting Buddhist spirituality towards a more fulfilling secular life.

Harris recently tweeted a link to his speech at the 2012 Global Atheist Convention, entitled "Death and the Present Moment."  Never content to let the audience merely wallow in their shared disrespect for belief in the supernatural, he brings up what tends to be the elephant in the room among antagonistic atheists: the simple fact that a belief in the afterlife does bring people a great amount of comfort, and that a destruction of that belief can lead to a rather violent rude awakening to the injustice and overall absurdity of life on Earth.  Nobody's beliefs should be influenced by a desire to escape uncomfortable truths, and any serious religious folk would agree, but I'm glad Harris brought up this topic because, as he mentions, atheism is nothing more than a way of "clearing the space for better conversations" about the art of living.  The funny part is that it seems like these "better conversations" consist largely of reclaiming leftover pieces from the religious beliefs that had to be "cleared" out of the way in the first place.

So, how does Harris propose the modern infidel deal with suffering and finitude?  He notices that "If we're right, and nothing happens after death, death, therefore, is not a problem.  Life is the problem.  The problem is that, without God...life appears to be an emergency."  The constant demands of living in reality, Harris claims, are constantly tearing us away from well-being and towards stress and neuroticism.  A solution to this natural flight from the present into the future, linked to the decline from mindful appreciation to irritable discontentment, is the Buddhist practice of mindfulness meditation.  Harris takes it upon himself to lead his audience in a complimentary trial of this spiritual technique, advising them to avoid being swayed too much by their various 'objects of thought.'

I think here would be a good place to mention Slavoj Zizek.  Zizek, a self-professed Christian materialist, notes in his book The Puppet and the Dwarf: The Perverse Core of Christianity that Harris' brand of spiritualism can function rather well as a tool of harmful political ideology, currently leading people to become ultimately indifferent to some of the less-than-appealing aspects of global state capitalism; I wonder if it's just a coincidence that Harris, in his litany of uncomfortable truths and absurdities the modern man is presented with, mentions the dismal conditions of the workers who make Apple products in China and elsewhere.  Zizek would likely say that the way to find true well-being in the face of such suffering would not be to discount 'thought objects' of future justice in order to accept the present as it is, but rather to make that future a reality by working ceaselessly for it in the present, losing not one's attachment to justice, but rather one's attachments to inner peace and even survival.  In other words, you can only really live by finding something you'd be willing to die for; a world of emergency is, therefore, full of opportunities for truly meaningful existence.

This concern regarding indifference to injustice finds its object in Harris's talk about the conscience.  "If you're constantly ruminating on what you just did, or what you should've done, or would've done if only you'd had the chance, you will miss your life," warns Harris.  "The conversation we have with ourselves every every minute of the day comes at a cost.  I'm not saying that discursive thought is not necessary or useful, but it is the mechanism by which most of our suffering is inflicted."  Harris paid his respects to the late Christopher Hitchens in the beginning, but hearing this part of the speech reminded me of Hitchens's praise for the "inner witness" as the primary source of morality, and I don't think Harris's own view on 'ethical intuitions subject to rational justification' is much different.  So, it would seem that Sam Harris, champion of secular ethics, in this speech advocates for a moral moderation of sorts.  But is this much better than the so-called religious moderation that he so (rightfully) detests?  If one's ethical intuitions must be domesticated and controlled to avoid stress, then how does one know when to actually pay attention to them?

The problem when life stops appearing emergent is is one of boredom and anxiety.  What is there to do once you've escaped the vicious incarnate cycle of attachment to virtue?  No action can be justified or condemned, not even by one's own 'objects of thought.'  Real anxiety comes not with moral sensitivity, but at a distance from the self-evident validity of those stress-inducing ethical intuitions.

Yet, this is not a problem for Harris or the Buddha.  They do not discount all the value of human well-being, but take it upon themselves to spread their teachings into the rest of the world.  Like Christ, who "Being in very nature God, did not consider equality with God something to be grasped, but made himself nothing, taking the very nature of a servant" (Philippians 2:6-7), Sidhartha Gautama, being in very nature Enlightened, gave up the isolated bliss of nirvana by investing himself in the spread of wisdom throughout the world.  As Harris tries to bring back morality without anxiety and guilt, so too Jesus "Redeemed us from the curse of the Law" (Galatians 3:13), forgiving past sins without destroying the role of morality as an imperative to progress.  Once detachment has been achieved, re-attachment or Christian love can be chosen by a free choice, in spite of the suffering that comes with it.

What if Buddhism, like Atheism, is just a way of "clearing the space for better conversations?"  What if those conversations lead back from detachment and nirvana to a conscious embrace of attachment and its resultant suffering?  Zizek wants to set Christianity and Marxism in opposition to a bourgeois spiritual detachment from significance, but it seems like the love and sacrifice of Christ may only be fully understood through the Buddhist lens of attachment and nirvana.  Next time you're faced with a moral dilemma, be sure to ask yourself: "What Would the Buddha, Jesus, and Sam Harris Do?"

Saturday, June 2, 2012

Meaning Like We Mean It


by Benny Mattis


This is a response to John R. Searle's "Chinese Room" argument that I originally wrote for Louise Antony's Philosophy of Mind class in Fall 2011.  This paper also won the UMASS Amherst Philosophy Department's Jonathan Edwards Prize in 2012.
*****

Meaning Like We Mean It

The Chinese Room
Philosopher of mind John R. Searle, in an article entitled “Can Computers Think?” argues that minds are not merely programs that can be run on digital computers, but rather effects of some “causal powers” of the brain.  Searle makes clear that, while the causal powers of the brain are capable of producing something called “semantic meaning” or “intentionality” or “mental states,” mere programs for digital computers have no way of producing those phenomena, since they are only syntactical abstractions and devoid of any semantic content.
He makes this point by performing a thought experiment called the “Chinese Room.”  The experiment places Searle in a room with a “large batch of Chinese writing” (417), which is indistinguishable to him (unable to read Chinese) from “ meaningless squiggles” (418).  This assortment of squiggles, unbeknownst to Searle, is called a “story” by the organizers of the experiment (418).  Additionally, he is given a second “batch” of squiggles along with rules in English on “How to correlate the second batch with the first” batch” (this set is secretly called “questions), as well as English instructions on how to reply to combinations of squiggles from the second batch with members of a third batch of squiggles; this third batch is called “answers” by the hypothetical organizers of this experiment (418).  In short, Searle is given all the tools he needs to answer questions in Chinese about a story written and read in Chinese, all without actually “understanding” a single character of Chinese.
Searle compares this “Chinese subsystem” with an “English subsystem” wherein he is simply given a story in English, followed by questions about the story, which he can answer with the full knowledge of what his words are describing.  Searle maintains that no matter how complex the English instructions (analogous to a computer program) are, the Chinese squiggles will be no more “understood” in their semantic meaning in the same way that the story, questions, and answers in English are understood (418).  This notion is set in opposition to the thesis of Strong A.I., which views the problem of creating artificial mental states as simply a problem of designing the correct program; if Strong A.I. is correct, the Chinese subsystem could be said to “understand” the semantic meaning of the conversation if only the program were written properly.  Searle suggests that the essence of intentionality is not in the realization of a computer program, but rather in some other “causal powers” of the brain (424).  This conclusion evokes a plethora of responses, to which he replies somewhat unsatisfactorily at times, especially regarding the specific requirements for semantic meaning to obtain in any given biological or mechanical machine.
Clarifying the Problem
Programs as syntactical structures could very well exist as thinking minds in the same way that shapes “exist” as real objects or groups of objects.  Shapes do not have any “causal powers” necessary to realize them, other than functional organization; likewise, there is no reason to believe that there must be some “causal powers” in addition to mere functional organization in order to produce an actual mind.  The sun, for example, might be an example of a sphere.  Does this mean that ‘anything which causes a sphere to exist must have causal powers at least equal to those of the sun?’  Of course not; the only thing needed to be a sphere is for some matter or energy to fit a certain functional pattern.  Likewise, on the view of Strong A.I., the only thing needed to realize intentionality is for a machine to run a certain functional program.
If nothing realizes a mind-program, then there are no minds instantiated, and quite obviously no meaning attached to any symbols at all.  The program is just an abstract syntactical structure, which in fact is incapable of referring to anything in reality.  Even if another step is taken, and this program is realized, it is incapable of semantic meaning if it is not given anything real to attach meaning to—a string of inputs, for example, via a keyboard, light sensor, or other object sensitive to the outside world.  Bruce Bridgeman thoughtfully remarked in his reply to Searle that, “A program lying on a tape spool in a corner is no more conscious than a brain preserved in a glass jar” (427).  A computer program is not an existing mind until it has been instantiated and given inputs.  However, once it starts getting tangled up in reality, semantics could become not only possible but even inevitable.
The Secret Life of Thermostats
When a calculator makes a calculation given some inputs, it is actually performing certain cognitive processes (regardless of whether it is self-aware) and giving an output that really means something about reality.  It may only manipulate symbols based on how they are represented in relation to each other (much like the squiggles Searle manipulated in the thought experiment), but that is all that mathematicians are doing when they manipulate quantities (which are only known in relation to each other) according to memorized rules.  In this way, the warming and cooling activity of a thermostat also means something about the belief- and desire-states of the thermostat, which are directly related to the world around it.  In Searle’s Chinese room, there is semantic meaning attached by virtue of the system itself to input and output symbols, regardless of whether anyone actually understands the meaning.
It may not be surprising that Searle does not agree with this ascription of semantic ability to an object as rudimentary as a calculator.  In his rebuttals, Searle differentiates between “intrinsic” and “observer-relative” ascriptions of intentionality (452).  Human beings have intrinsic intentionality, because they know what their actions and words will mean to an observer, but the thermostat does not understand its own actions at all; an intelligent observer is necessary for its actions to be understood in relation to the temperature and settings in objective reality.  Thus, Searle would say that any intentionality a calculator has is strictly observer-relative.  Searle remarks that we speak as if thermostats have beliefs “Not because we suppose they have a mental life much like our own; on the contrary, we know they have no mental life at all” (452).  It seems quite obvious to Searle that the beliefs of simple mechanisms are not only different from those of people, but entirely nonexistent.
The dichotomy between “a mental life much like our own” and “no mental life at all” is questionable at best.  No functionalist or believer in Strong A.I. would say that the experience of a thermostat is similar to that of a human; under those views, the experiences would only be similar to the extent that the thermostat’s functional organization resembles that of the human brain.  The thermostat is not aware of how its actions appear to an outside observer, and therefore cannot intend to express an idea the same way one person can intend to communicate with another; it does, however, by its very nature compute thermal inputs and respond appropriately, and this could very well be considered a proper type of mentality.
At this point, it makes sense to question whether full consciousness is necessary for intention or semantics.  An intoxicated, barely-conscious individual presents a problem for this assumption:  if “Bob” becomes too acquainted with his favorite substance, for example, he may begin to say things without actually intending to express those ideas beforehand.  It is clear that a certain type of intention is missing in Bob’s case; he is incapable of assessing himself through an approximated observer’s perspective and acting appropriately to express his feelings.  I do not think, however, that Searle would suggest that Bob lacks the ability to express semantically meaningful statements. 
Bob’s words semantically mean the same thing that they would mean if he uttered them sober.  Bob could not change this fact even if he wanted to; thus, the inevitability of semantic meaning.  If we picture Bob doing math, his mathematics would not be meaningless or unintentional merely because he is not in a state of perpetual reflection on the concept of quantity and the axioms on which his math is based.  Likewise, a computer’s calculations or the calculated heat adjustments of a thermostat are not rendered semantically meaningless by the mere fact that they are not conscious of their own cognitive acts, or what those acts are ‘about.’  It would be absurd to claim that a calculator has the same mind as a mathematician, but it is plausible that the aspect of a mathematician’s mind involved in adding and subtracting numbers could be instantiated in a calculator with sufficient operational similarity to the their mental problem-solving method.
The fact that there is a fixed causal relation between the inputs and the outputs in the Chinese room, akin to the relation between the problems given to a drunken mathematician and his or her reflexively scribbled solutions, is the source of the semantic content of what it says; it does not merely make it possible for people with brains to ascribe meaning to them, as Searle suggests, but rather it is the source of the meaning itself.
From Calculators to Terminators
Searle would likely respond to this idea in the way he responded to a number of other replies to his article in Behavioral and Brain Sciences (452):
Even if formal tokens in the program have some causal connection to their alleged referents in the real world, as long as the agent has no way of knowing that, it adds no intentionality whatever to the formal states.
There are two possibilities I find likely that Searle refers to when he says, “The agent has no way of knowing that.”  The first is that the symbol does not inspire a mental representation of the referent when it reaches the person in the room, or the central processing unit in a computer.  The second interpretation is that the person in the room has no idea that the symbols given to him are even connected to the outside world at all.
            The former interpretation suggests that Searle’s problem, and indeed the problem with common intuition, is that “The English subsystem knows that ‘hamburger’ means hamburger.  The Chinese subsystem knows only that squiggle squiggle is followed by squoggle squoggle” (453).  I do not believe that there is as big a difference as Searle suspects between these two semantic relations.  The Chinese system gets a squiggle squiggle, relates it to a series of rules on the grammar of “squiggle squiggle” and the squiggle’s relation to others recorded in the system’s memory (for example, “squiggle squiggle has relation X to snuggle duggle) and outputs “squoggle squoggle” in an appropriate way.  The human sees “hamburger,” decodes the visual stimuli and matches them with an associated cluster of stimuli (the “hamburger-concept”), and outputs a response based on its memory or “belief-state.”  Thus, it appears that concepts of concrete objects, like formal mathematical quantities and Chinese “squiggles,” are known only in relation to each other.
Could not the networked relations of squiggles in the Chinese room (or, indeed, those of binary symbols in a digitally programmed computer) be made in a way similar to those that the English-speaking human draws upon intuitively upon hearing “hamburger?”  The Chinese room is disposed to relate inputs to outputs with the use of past inputs; the human is disposed to relate sense-data to actions based on past sense-data (for example, the memory of eating or hearing about a hamburger).  There is no reason not to believe that an isomorphic similarity between the two would be sufficient to produce intentionality, whether such similarity be realized in a death-dealing android or a Turing machine made of toilet paper.
With that counterintuitive notion, we can move on to the second interpretation of Searle’s response: how, in fact, does the person in the Chinese room know that a Chinese hamburger squiggle even refers to anything concrete at all?  Putting oneself in the shoes of the man in the Chinese room, it seems quite obvious that a certain sense of what is “real” is lost—everything in the Chinese subsystem is mediated through strange symbols.
            That sense of what is “real” may be just that—a sense.  Rene Descartes noted the possibility that all of one’s senses are an illusion, and Searle himself even remarks how intentional states are not a matter of the outside world, but rather private mental phenomena: “It is the operation of the brain and not the impart of the outside world that matters for the content of our intentional states, at least in one important sense of the word ‘content’” (452).  As many modern philosophers are all too aware, we do not know for a fact that our words really refer to anything outside of arrangements of related concepts in our minds; the fact that Searle acknowledges this suggests that this is not what he meant by “The agent has no way of knowing that,” but it is a topic worth bringing up anyway, and sheds light on why the Chinese subsystem seems to be different from the English one.  We act according to the inputs we are given, and produce outputs based on our memory and tendency to pursue certain goals, just like the man in the Chinese room.
            Why, then, does the English subsystem seem so different from the Chinese subsystem in the Chinese Room experiment?  The subject actually does not know as much in the English subsystem as he does in the Chinese subsystem.  In the Chinese subsystem, the alienation of Searle’s responses from their referents is made explicit; he is only acting by relating formal symbols to another, such as the squiggle for “hamburger” with the squoggle for “ketchup,” and as a result the absurdity of his formal operations are brought to the fore.  In the English subsystem, Searle is faced with a feeling that he ‘knows what he is talking about.’  He is still only manipulating formal packets of quantitative sense-data (the probability of concurrence of taste-value K and taste-value H, perhaps), but his intimate familiarity with those packets produces in him the illusion of a special connection to the outside universe. 
Programs Writing Programs
Now, it’s possible that one can never know for sure whether what it’s like to be a robot is similar to what it’s like to be a person; we can never verify beyond doubt that a computer feels “thoughts, feelings, and the rest of the forms of intentionality” (450) in the same way we do, just as we can never verify beyond a doubt that even John R. Searle has such feelings.  The fact that a thermostat probably lacks a mental life like our own, however, does not necessitate that it has nothing resembling mentality at all.  There is no reason to believe that functional organization is not, in fact, the property that gives the brain its “causal powers” to produce consciousness and intention.  This leads to seemingly ridiculous results, such as the possibility of a water-pump computer gaining consciousness, but I would dare say that it is not harder to believe than the suggestion that intentionality is “Likely to be as causally dependent on the specific biochemistry of its origins as lactation, photosynthesis, or any other biological phenomena” (424).  This is weird stuff.
            Neither human nor computer actually knows whether their internal tokens refer to anything external.  Both human and computer ascribe semantic meaning to tokens gathered from reality by associating them with each other according to rule-bound functional relations.  The question of whether their mental states are similar remains open.  Strong A.I. may still be wrong when it comes to consciousness, but it also may be right—when it comes to semantics, however, a denial of such power to artificial intelligence would also put our own abilities in question, as Bob’s example demonstrates.  By virtue of being instantiated in the real world and being given input, a computer ascribes meaning to that input (by a fixed relation between interconnected symbols with their own hidden causal connections to an external reality) and produces an output, which also means something relative to the input and the program’s internal states.  This is, for our purposes, indistinguishable from a brain taking sense-data from the real world, relating it to other packs of sense-data, and producing an output which means something relative to the input and the person’s internal states.  A computer, like a person, ascribes meaning to its inputs and outputs by virtue of the fact that it exists and is consistently causally connected with the real world—it may be challenging to learn the language they are processing symbols in, but there is a language in both cases nonetheless, semantic reference included.  Most importantly, all of these similarities apply regardless of what material the machine is made of; whether gray matter or water pipes, a program instantiated produces equally semantically meaningful output, whether it “means to” or not.

Works Cited
Searle, John R.  “Minds, Brains, and Programs.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 1980: 3, 417-457. Print.

Friday, June 1, 2012

I Told You

by Benny Mattis

This is the entry I wrote (anonymously at first) and read aloud for the 2012 issue of the exceptional Gordon College publication, If I Told You.  It was a really great experience, and I'm glad they accepted my entry even though I was no longer attending the 'Gord.
*****

        One year ago, I was preparing myself to attend a secular school for the first time in more than ten years.   I did not know what to expect in the upcoming semester; I was raised in a conservative Christian household and educated in Christian private schools since fourth grade, and the way some of my friends and family talked about the public university, it sounded more like a temple of Satan than a respected educational institution.  Either way, I knew I needed to find a community that was not based entirely on ideas that I had come to disagree with; I left the church in my third semester of college, and had to leave Gordon as well.
            Socrates is cited as father of the famous maxim, “The unexamined life is not worth living.”  If there’s one thing I’ve learned in the past year, however, it is that the examined life is worth living.  Too often in our society, skepticism is painted as the “shadow of doubt,” a maleficent state of mind which ought to be avoided like the plague; on the contrary, the ability to seek and accept the truth often precedes an ability to act in accordance with it.  Skepticism is not a shadow itself; it’s only the opening of one’s eyes to find that one is in the dark.  Once the eyes are open, a search for the light switch can begin.
            If you’ve just opened your eyes in the dark, you may feel a little nervous or lonely; you may expect your friends not to care about your thoughts, or worse.  True—talking about doubt and apostasy with your friends is never as safe a subject as, say, the weather of the past week.  But once again, at least for me, it was not nearly as bad as it could have been.  When I made my problems with Christianity known, I was told by someone that some acquaintances of mine had made fun of me behind my back for it—this was bothersome, but I only learned that those friends weren’t really worth my time.  The best of my friends understood me, and while a relationship is not the same without shared beliefs in the supernatural, one based on trust and honesty is vastly more authentic and meaningful than they would have been had I kept things to myself.  Despite transferring from Gordon, I feel like I’m closer to some of my Gordon friends than ever before.
            The same thing happened with my family, though that was a bit more difficult in the early stages.  I was actually worrying about whether they would kick me out of the house when I told them I was leaving the church—I value honesty pretty highly, though, so I decided not to misrepresent myself for temporary comfort.  My parents were upset; they took it a little personally, that I would reject the teachings they raised me with.  There were tears when I told them I left the church, and more tears a few months later, when I told them I had become an atheist.  They did not kick me out of the house, however, and while we can’t help but hurt each other emotionally sometimes, honesty really has been the best policy regarding relationships with friends and family.
            While honesty with others is really the only path to authentic relationships, it is also brings to light differences among your friends and family you may have preferred remaining unacquainted with.  I was shocked at the fact that some people simply don’t care about the truth or falsity of religion, and this difference of interests is something that every skeptic has to grapple with.  On all sides of the spectrum, you will have people telling you to silence yourself: Christians will be telling you to ignore your rationality, atheists will be telling you to ignore your gut feelings, and agnostics will be telling you to give up on the enterprise as a whole.  I suggest you ignore all of these requests—spiritual or rational suicide will only prevent you from reaching your full potential as a person.  It’s much more fulfilling to dive into reality with every fiber of your being, reconciled or otherwise, trying to make sense of it all.  As the famous agnostic Clarence Darrow once said, “Chase the truth like all hell and you’ll free yourself, even though you never touch its coattails.”
            For all the grand narratives built around the search for truth, however, skepticism itself is not an idol worthy of religious devotion.  As the Enlightenment philosopher David Hume advised, “Be a philosopher, but amid all your philosophy be still a man” (or woman).  Remember your friends and family when God is nowhere to be found.  Remember your conscience when friends and family fall away as well.  Enjoy your life and live it to the fullest—I believe philosophy is necessary in this mission, but it is far from sufficient. 
-Alumnus, Class of 2013

Legos and the Meaning of Life

by Benny Mattis

This is another blog from my time at Gordon College.

***

There are some kids who go to a preschool. "Good Bricks" are the new cool thing, and so these kids get some Good Bricks from their parents. The kids have difficulty deciphering and following the instructions for assembling these bricks, but they figure them out eventually. The kids who decipher the instructions make cool creations, and the kids who can't follow the directions correctly make crappy ones.

One of the kids wonders, "Hey, who made these instructions anyway?"
The rest of them reply, "The Good Bricks 'Master Builders' made these instructions, and they are obviously the source of all that is cool." The kids continue to follow the instructions, and get better and better sets to feed their imaginations.

Then, Good Bricks comes out with a new product line, called "Trionicle." Some of the kids say, "Wow, what will the Master Builders think of next? These toys are totally different!" But some kids say "No, the Good Bricks company has totally fleeced you with their advertising and feature films. These Trionicle toys are just shitty humanoid robot-looking things; they're not good bricks at all!" There is no longer a uniform view of what is "cool," and the kids split into two camps-- the Good Brickers and the Old Schoolers. The Old Schoolers no longer look to the instructions to determine what is cool; they differentiate between cool Good Bricks and uncool Good Bricks with their own sense of coolness. The Good Brickers say that all Good Bricks are cool, because Good Bricks epitomizes coolness.

Soon, the Old Schoolers become bored of the limited selection of cool Good Bricks. They say, hey, lets take our creations apart and try to make something ourselves. Some of their new creations are cool, and some of them are uncool.

The Good Brickers are astonished at this; if the Master Builders are the source of all coolness, how can these Old Schoolers make these cool new designs? The leader of the Good Brickers says that this is because the Old Schoolers are just copying what the Master Builders have already made. The Good Brickers breathe a sigh of relief, and continue to dissociate themselves from the Old Schoolers.

However, the Good Bricks company is going down the tubes. Its designs are becoming progressively more worthless, but the Old Schoolers are making creations more original and cool than anything the Masters ever built. Moreover, all the other students are getting GameStations, because the GameStation is advertised way more than Good Bricks. So, many of the Good Brickers join the Old Schoolers, admitting that the Master Builders are not the only source of coolness. Some Good Brickers hold their ground, but they can never find spots at the lunch tables.

Now, there is a solid group of Old Schoolers, and they realize that if there is not a major spike in demand for bricks, Good Bricks will go bankrupt, and they will never be able to buy more bricks. The rest of the school is convinced that GameStation is the sole source of coolness, and some kids are even saying things like "Nothing is cool, because it's all going to be in a landfill in 50 years anyway." The Old Schoolers, affected by this ignorance in their community and wishing to show how cool brick-assembly is, spread the coolness of Good Bricks until summer vacation.

----

Meanwhile, the Good Bricks Master Builders and advertisers are asking the million dollar question, "What is coolness?"
They realize that in different countries and different eras, what is "cool" changes depending on a product's place in time and space. In the 1990s, dinosaur sets were very cool. In the 80s, the advent of personal computing made futuristic brick sets cool. Different circumstances produced different standards for what is cool.

However, there are certain criteria for coolness that remained constant through all of their records. It is cool, for example, to include a protagonist and an antagonist in the backstories of their brick sets. It is cool to make a set that can really stimulate a kid's imagination. It is cool to include some sort of romantic interest for the hero, as well.

Good Bricks went out of business. The designers broke into GameStation game-design companies. The companies that made games in accordance with the general norms of coolness thrived, but the designers who ignored these guides went bankrupt. The Master Designers were bound by the nature of coolness; they could not succeed unless their designs were in accordance with it. And as their designs conformed more and more to "natural coolness," more and more people thought that the Designers were in fact the epitome of all that is cool. Even though coolness can come from places other than the minds of the Master Designers, the ideas of "cool" and "Master Designer" became increasingly intertwined.

Eventually, it became nearly impossible to differentiate between the two. Only by looking back at the history of diverse attempts at coolness were people able to see that coolness comes not from the Master Designers, but out of the nature of a relationship between gamer, game and environment; the Master Designers simply study this relationship and use it to their advantage (and, ultimately, to the advantage of someone who buys their game).