by Benny Mattis
The
Two-Way Street
In
his book Where the
Conflict Really Lies,
Christian philosopher Alvin Plantinga argues that any actual
conflicts between science and religion are merely superficial,
justifying his claim with the following reasoning:
- Scientific theories that are inconsistent with Christian belief “do not constitute or provide a defeater for the Christian beliefs with which they conflict” (xiii).
- If (1), then (3).
- Thus, the conflict (if any) between Christian belief and the theories in question is superficial.
Plantinga
rationalizes the first premise of this valid argument compellingly in
the section of his book entitled “Superficial Conflict,” but
seems to think that (2) does not require justification; in fact, the
premise is not explicitly stated anywhere in the relevant section of
the text, despite its importance in his main argument.
Some
might find the verity of (2) self-evident, but this is not the case.
Consider, as a counterexample, the case where Christian
belief constitutes or
provides a defeater for the scientific
theories in question.
In this case, (3) would seem to be false, though (1) would still be
true. The conditional in (2), therefore, does not seem to hold.
Without rationales for deriving (3) from (1), Plantinga’s assertion
of the superficiality of the conflict (if any) between science and
religion remains insufficiently justified.
This
is not to say that Plantinga provides no argument against the
existence of deep science/religion conflict. Premise (1) presupposes
that the theories in question are indeed proper science, but
Plantinga notes this may not be the case (163). He suggests that the
theories in question do not really constitute claims about the actual
world, but rather claims about how things seem
from a certain perspective (182), in which case there would only be
an apparent
conflict (that would be appropriately called “superficial,” but
also merely “alleged”). These solutions, however, require
Plantinga to deny his given premise that they are, in fact, real
conflicts between science and theistic belief.
Alvin
Plantinga's Adequatio
Intellectus Ad Intellectus
In
the section entitled "Deep Concord" of his book Where
the Conflict Really Lies,
Alvin Plantinga counts Hume's problem of induction (that is, the
apparent lack of logical justification for inductive inferences about
the future based on the past) as not a problem for inductive
reasoning, but rather an example of the adequatio
intellectus ad rem, or
curious fit between human understanding and reality, of whose
existence theism is presumably a better explanation than naturalism.
"Its success is one more example of the fit between our
cognitive faculties and the world," Plantinga claims (295),
implying that "the world is in such a way that inductive
reasoning is successful" (296). His logic appears to be as
follows:
1)
"The world is in such a way that inductive reasoning is
successful."
2)
If (1), then (3).
3)
So, there is a "fit between [inductive reasoning] and the
world."
This
argument is valid; in fact, it may even be sound. However, it is
also trivial; in speaking of induction's "success" in
general, Plantinga appears to be begging Hume's question of whether,
in fact, "there is a fit between [inductive reasoning] and the
world." The only apparent rationale for (1) is itself based on
inductive reasoning, as follows:
1a)
There have been instances where inductive reasoning was successful.
1b)
If (1a), then (1c).
1c)
There is a "fit between [inductive reasoning] and the world."
Premise
(1b), an inductive inference from past instances to the state of the
world at all times, is only justified given (3). The conclusion of
Plantinga's argument is necessary to justify his premises; he is
begging Hume's question. Plantinga here merely shows a fit between
intellect (induction) and intellect, rather than between intellect
and reality.
Plantinga's
Mission: Impossible
In
Where the Conflict
Really Lies, Plantinga
suggests that, even if each instance of content in a mental belief
has a neurophysiological (or "NP") property equivalent to
it "in the broadly logical sense," it is still rational to
speak of specific consequences of hypothetical scenarios wherein
"belief B had the same NP properties but different content"
(337-338). He appears to justify this by analogy:
1)
There are instances where "Philosophers regularly and quite
properly use counterpossibles in arguing for their views" (338).
2)
If (1), then (3).
3)
Therefore, Plantinga's use of a counterpossible in his response is
rational.
This
argument is valid, and Plantinga justifies (1) with the example of
the dualist-materialist debate; either dualism or materialism is
necessarily false, but debaters on both sides rationally discuss what
would
happen if their opponents were correct (despite thinking that such
situations are counterpossible) (339). The verity of premise (2),
however, is dependent on whether Plantinga's use of a counterpossible
is relevantly similar to such examples, and, in fact, it is not.
Given
dualism, it would be a direct contradiction to speak of what happens
given materialism, and hence irrational. Debating with materialists,
however, the dualist must argue as if dualism were not
given--to do otherwise would be begging the question. Likewise,
given that content is equivalent to a neurophysiological property, it
is as rational to say "the same content but different NP
properties" as it is to say "the same content but not the
same content," from which anything follows. However, the
materialist does not have to argue as if this equivalence were not
given, because it is not what is up for debate; what is up for debate
in Plantinga's discussion is the probability of certain states of
affairs given
materialism, naturalism, and evolution.
Plantinga
attempts to clarify his point by succinctly asserting that
"clearly...it is in virtue of its neurophysiological properties
that [a belief] B causes [an action] A...It isn't by virtue of having
that particular content." However, given
that content is logically
equivalent to its
actual correlative NP properties, then once again, Plantinga's
rationale for (1) is an outright contradiction.
The
Indication of Belief
Premise
(1) of Plantinga's Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism (EAAN)
depends heavily on his assertion that, as he writes in Science
and Religion,
"indication is not belief...and accurate indication need not be
accompanied by true belief. As long as the indication is accurate,
the belief content can be anything whatsoever" (70). Plantinga
defends these claims with examples, including one involving a frog
that reflexively flicks its tongue out to catch a nearby insect:
1)
Accurate indication is necessary for the frog's survival (69).
2)
True belief is not necessary for the frog's survival (69).
3)
So, "indication is not belief...and accurate indication need
not be accompanied by true belief." (70).
The
first clause of (3) seems to follow from (1) and (2), but it does not
follow from that fact that accurate indication could
be accompanied by false beliefs, or that the naturalist has any
reason to think that beliefs in general on naturalism are not
truth-aimed.
Premise
(3) is also vague. Plantinga's claim that "indication is not
belief" can mean one of two things:
B1)
All indication is such that it is not belief.
B2)
Not all indication is such that it is belief.
(B2)
follows from (1) and (2); (B1) does not. The principle of charity
thus demands us to assume that Plantinga was referring to (B2). Now
consider the proposition that belief is actually a type
of indicator:
B3)
Some indication is belief, and all belief is indication.
This
proposition is perfectly compatible with (B2), the conclusion of
Plantinga's thought experiment with the frog. However, if beliefs
(and the other cognitive faculties in question) are a type of
indicator, and indicators in general tend to be accurate given
evolution, then the reliability of our cognitive faculties, given
that we have
cognitive faculties, is highly probable given naturalism,
materialism, and evolution. This does, in fact, seem like a quite
sensible way of looking at beliefs--it appears, then, that the
naturalist really ought to believe in the reliability of their
cognitive faculties, even given their unguided origins.
Work
Cited
Plantinga,
Alvin. Where the
Conflict Really Lies.
Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2011.
Print.
No comments:
Post a Comment
What did you think?